传奇是什么意思| 知己什么意思| 茱萸是什么植物| 白目是什么意思| 尿隐血阴性是什么意思| 脑萎缩是什么病| 总胆红素高说明什么| 告辞是什么意思| 吃布洛芬不能吃什么| 冻豆腐炖什么好吃| 卫青为什么被灭九族| 癞蛤蟆长什么样| 精神分裂症吃什么药| 女性出汗多是什么原因| 10月28日是什么日子| 韬略是什么意思| 前列腺液是什么样子| 刘封为什么不救关羽| 常山现在叫什么| 吃什么养颜美容抗衰老| 胎毒是什么意思| 人模狗样是什么生肖| 自愈是什么意思| 8月8号是什么日子| 月经期间适合吃什么食物| 赤诚相见是什么意思| 阴唇内侧长疙瘩是什么原因| 槟榔中间的膏是什么| 哮喘有什么症状| 胳膊上种花是什么疫苗| 冠状动脉钙化什么意思| 加味逍遥丸和逍遥丸有什么区别| 命中劫是什么意思| 为什么飞机撞鸟会坠机| 长绒棉和全棉什么区别| 一心一意什么意思| 口腔医学学什么| 大便遇水就散什么原因| resp是什么意思| 笑字五行属什么| 为什么一| 右脚浮肿预示着什么| 420是什么意思| 男女双修是什么意思| 音乐制作人是干什么的| 流水生财是什么意思| 投桃报李是什么生肖| 骨髓炎是什么病| 沂字五行属什么| 附件炎是什么引起的| 不惑之年是什么意思| 藜麦是什么东西| hpv56阳性是什么意思| 腋臭去医院挂什么科| 处女座和什么座最配| 里正相当于现在什么官| 胃病能吃什么水果| 什么杯子喝水最健康| 菠菜不能和什么一起吃| 范仲淹号什么| 尿葡萄糖是什么意思| 降调针什么时候打| 排卵期会有什么症状| 青盐是什么盐| 白血球高是什么原因| 后卫是什么意思| 尿路感染吃什么药| 三焦指的是什么| 秋葵什么季节吃| 小寨附近有什么好玩的| 什么情| 妥瑞氏症是什么病| 测幽门螺旋杆菌挂什么科| 减肥期间吃什么水果好| 血压正常心跳快是什么原因| 庭字五行属什么| 鸡蛋散黄是什么原因| 哺乳期吃什么食物好| 可望不可求是什么意思| 中午12点是什么时辰| 今年67岁属什么生肖| 黄桃不能和什么一起吃| 人体自由基是什么| timing是什么意思| 检查胸部应该挂什么科| 10月23号是什么星座| cc代表什么意思| 肾结石有什么症状| jordan是什么牌子| 董酒是什么香型| 兆后面的单位是什么| 这叫什么| 麻风病是什么症状图片| 牡丹是什么意思| 珮字五行属什么| 抑郁症吃的药叫什么| 四不像是指什么动物| 子宫息肉有什么症状| 频繁感冒是什么原因| 生是什么意思| 牙出血什么原因| 憋不住尿什么原因| hy什么意思| 曹曦月演过什么电视剧| 什么叫窦性心律不齐| 性功能减退吃什么药| 洁身自好什么意思| 烦躁不安的意思是什么| 高五行属什么| 沐浴露什么牌子好| 7月6日是什么星座| 海扶治疗是什么| 右后背疼什么原因| 怀孕了吃什么药能打掉| 和女生聊什么话题| 意志力是什么意思| 高血糖是什么原因引起的| 菜花炒什么好吃| 什么叫双开| 政委是干什么的| apl医学上是什么意思| 娘娘命是什么样的命| 拯救银河系什么意思| 孔子是什么家| 屁股下垂穿什么裤子| 金达莱是什么花| bur什么意思| 朝鲜和韩国是什么关系| 金牛男和什么星座女最配| mcg是什么意思| 手指甲软薄是缺什么| 心血管狭窄吃什么药| logo是什么| 懒散是什么意思| cg动画是什么意思| 乳痈是什么病| 11月份生日是什么星座| fans是什么意思| 男性尿血是什么原因导致的| 番茄是什么时候传入中国的| 痛风吃什么菜好| 胸骨疼挂什么科| 鸭子吃什么食物| 拉肚子发烧是什么原因| 阿司匹林不能和什么药一起吃| 淞字五行属什么| 甲减有什么症状表现| 医保定点是什么意思| 子宫内膜粘连有什么症状| 7月14号是什么节日| 结婚的礼数都有什么| 冬阴功汤都放什么食材| 工程院院士是什么级别| 日语为什么| 宫颈糜烂什么症状| 拉肚子胃疼吃什么药| au585是什么金| 头皮痒用什么止痒最好| 今年66岁属什么生肖的| 什么品种的西瓜最好吃| 保肝护肝吃什么| 富贵包是什么| 房水是什么| 尿蛋白吃什么药| 叶酸不能和什么一起吃| 耄耋之年是什么意思| 长血痣是什么原因| 什么算高危性行为| 重庆有什么好大学| 干贝和瑶柱有什么区别| 肾炎什么症状| 尿液发绿是什么原因| 苦胆是什么| 排卵期一般是什么时候| 怀孕了梦见蛇是什么意思| 纷纷扬扬是什么意思| 冰箱保鲜室不制冷是什么原因| 什么止咳效果最好最快| 醒酒汤是什么| 最好的油是什么油| 上环什么时候去最合适| 内热吃什么药| 淋证是什么病| 避孕套什么牌子好用又安全| 卡哇伊内是什么意思| 反差是什么意思| 玉米不能和什么食物一起吃| 头热手脚冰凉什么原因| 乳酪和奶酪有什么区别| 可定什么时间服用最好| 悠悠是什么意思| uhd是什么意思| 夏天适合种植什么蔬菜| 形容高兴的词语有什么| 思的五行属性是什么| 淋巴滤泡增生是什么意思| 戴银镯子变黑是什么原因| 内痔有什么症状与感觉| 冷漠什么意思| 童瑶为什么要告黄定宇| 中医把脉能看出什么| 弱智是什么意思| 亚洲没有什么气候| 肝肾阴虚是什么原因引起的| 皮肤挂什么科| 为什么不建议治疗幽门螺杆菌| 吃什么可以降尿酸| 心包积液吃什么药| 中国是什么时区| 梦见狗咬别人是什么意思| apart是什么意思| 红米是什么米| 眼睛闪光是什么症状| 呼吸快是什么原因| 向日葵花代表什么意思| 股票pb是什么意思| 血小板低什么原因| 影字五行属什么| 牙疼吃什么饭菜比较好| 万足读什么| plus是什么意思| 五蕴皆空是什么意思| 26岁属什么的生肖| 贝贝什么意思| 减肥吃什么菜| 虎跟什么生肖相冲| 什么叫代孕| 光杆司令是什么意思| 质子泵抑制剂是什么药| 金牛和什么星座最配| 肺结节增殖灶什么意思| 脚出汗是什么原因| 咪咪头疼是什么原因| 日本为什么投降| 曾毅玲花什么关系| 萎靡是什么意思| 冬瓜有什么功效| 梦到自己怀孕是什么意思| 肾虚去医院挂什么科| 印尼用什么货币| 甲状腺囊肿不能吃什么| 牙髓炎是什么原因引起的| 嘴角烂是什么原因| 宝宝流鼻血是什么原因| 有什么寓言故事| 耳朵上长痘痘什么原因| 阑尾炎看什么科室| 淡盐水有什么作用和功效| 木须是什么| 七月十六号是什么星座| 张钧甯为什么读mi| 为什么会缺乏维生素d| 堆堆袜是什么| 女性漏尿是什么原因| 晚上八点半是什么时辰| 特别嗜睡是什么原因| 为什么会长疱疹| 被虫咬了挂什么科| 荨麻疹吃什么药最有效| 荆芥是什么| 为什么叫梅雨季节| 开诚布公什么意思| 男人结扎有什么危害| 王八羔子是什么意思| 百度Jump to content

qvod播放器下载(快播3.5不升级版)V5.20.238 不升级版

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 “车辆是否能适应这些极端路况,就成为一次次运输任务能否按时完成,乃至驾驶员生命安全能否得到保障的关键因素。

In argumentation theory, an argumentation scheme or argument scheme is a template that represents a common type of argument used in ordinary conversation. Many different argumentation schemes have been identified. Each one has a name (for example, argument from effect to cause) and presents a type of connection between premises and a conclusion in an argument, and this connection is expressed as a rule of inference. Argumentation schemes can include inferences based on different types of reasoningdeductive, inductive, abductive, probabilistic, etc.

The study of argumentation schemes (under various names) dates back to the time of Aristotle, and today argumentation schemes are used for argument identification, argument analysis, argument evaluation, and argument invention.

Some basic features of argumentation schemes can be seen by examining the scheme called argument from effect to cause, which has the form: "If A occurs, then B will (or might) occur, and in this case B occurred, so in this case A presumably occurred."[1]:?170? This scheme may apply, for example, when someone argues: "Presumably there was a fire, since there was smoke and if there is a fire then there will be smoke." This example looks like the formal fallacy of affirming the consequent ("If A is true then B is also true, and B is true, so A must be true"), but in this example the material conditional logical connective ("A implies B") in the formal fallacy does not account for exactly why the semantic relation between premises and conclusion in the example, namely causality, may be reasonable ("fire causes smoke"), while not all formally valid conditional premises are reasonable (such as in the valid modus ponens argument "If there is a cat then there is smoke, and there is a cat, so there must be smoke"). As in this example, argumentation schemes typically recognize a variety of semantic (or substantive) relations that inference rules in classical logic ignore.[2]:?19? More than one argumentation scheme may apply to the same argument; in this example, the more complex abductive argumentation scheme may also apply.

Overview

[edit]

Since the beginning of the discipline called rhetoric,[3] the study of the types of argument has been a central issue.[4][5][6] Knowledge of types of argument allows a speaker to find the argument form that is most suitable to a specific subject matter and situation. For example, arguments based on authority may be common in courts of law but not as frequent in a classroom discussion; arguments based on analogy are often effective in political discourse, but may be problematic in a scientific discussion.

The two interrelated goals of argument identification and analysis were the core of ancient dialectics (similar to debate), and specifically the branch called topics.[7][8][9] In the 20th century, the ancient interest in types of arguments was revived in several academic disciplines, including education, artificial intelligence, legal philosophy, and discourse analysis.[10]

The study of this ancient subject is mostly carried out today in the field of study called argumentation theory under the name of argumentation schemes.[1][11]

An example of an argumentation scheme is the scheme for argument from position to know given below.[12]:?86?

Argument from position to know
Premise: a is in a position to know whether A is true or false.
Assertion premise: a asserts that A is true ([or] false).
Conclusion: A may plausibly be taken to be true ([or] false).

Following the usual convention in argumentation theory, arguments are given as a list of premises followed by a single conclusion. The premises are the grounds given by the speaker or writer for the hearer or reader to accept the conclusion as true or as provisionally true (regarded as true for now). An argumentation scheme's definition is not itself an argument, but represents the structure of an argument of a certain type. The letters in the scheme, lower case a and upper case A, need to be filled in if an argument is to be created from the scheme. Lower case a would be replaced by the name of a person and upper case A by a proposition, which might be true or false.

Argumentation theorist Douglas N. Walton gives the following example of an argument that fits the argument from position to know scheme: "It looks as if this passer-by knows the streets, and she says that City Hall is over that way; therefore, let's go ahead and accept the conclusion that City Hall is that way."[12]:?86?

History

[edit]

Among 20th-century authors, Cha?m Perelman and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca may have been the first to write at length about argumentation schemes, which they called argumentative schemes.[13]:?9?[14]:?19? They present a long list of schemes together with explanation and examples in part three of The New Rhetoric (1958).[13] The argumentation schemes in The New Rhetoric are not described in terms of their logical structure, as in more recent scholarship on argumentation schemes; instead they are given prose descriptions. The structure of the arguments is, nevertheless, considered important by the authors.[13]:?187?

Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca also suggest a link between argumentation schemes and the loci (Latin) or topoi (Greek) of classical writers.[13]:?190? Both words, literally translated, mean "places" in their respective languages. Loci is a Latin translation of the Greek, topoi, used by Aristotle in his work, Topics, about logical argument and reasoning. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca explain loci as: "headings under which arguments can be classified".[13]:?83? And they write, "They are associated with a concern to help a speaker's inventive efforts and involve the grouping of relevant material, so that it can be easily found again when required."[13]:?83? While Aristotle's treatment of topoi is not the same as the modern treatment of argumentation schemes, it is reasonable to consider Aristotle as the first writer in the genre.[1]:?267?

The first contemporary writer to treat argumentation schemes in the way they are treated by current scholars and the way they are described in this article may have been Arthur Hastings in his 1962 Ph.D. dissertation.[15]

Forms of inference

[edit]

The study of argument in the field of argumentation theory since Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca's The New Rhetoric and Stephen Toulmin's The Uses of Argument,[16] both first published in 1958, has been characterized by a recognition of the defeasible, non-monotonic nature of most ordinary everyday arguments and reasoning.[14]:?615? A defeasible argument is one that can be defeated, and that defeat is achieved when new information is discovered that shows that there was a relevant exception to an argument in the presence of which the conclusion can no longer be accepted. A common example used in textbooks concerns Tweety, a bird that may or may not fly:[12]:?72–73?

(All) birds can fly;
Tweety is a bird;
Therefore, Tweety can fly.

This argument (with the addition of "All", which is shown in parentheses) has the form of a logical syllogism and is, therefore, valid. If the first two statements, the premises, are true, then the third statement, the conclusion, must also be true. However, if it is subsequently learned that Tweety is a penguin or has a broken wing, we can no longer conclude that Tweety can fly. In the context of deductive inference, we would have to conclude that the first premise was simply false. Deductive inference rules are not subject to exceptions. But there can be defeasible generalizations (defeasible inference rules). When we say that birds can fly, we mean that it is generally the case, subject to exceptions. We are justified in making the inference and accepting the conclusion that this particular bird can fly until we find out that an exception applies in this particular case.[17]:?21?

In addition to deductive inference and defeasible inference, there is also probabilistic inference.[12]:?65–69? A probabilistic version of the generalization, "birds can fly", might be: "There is a 75% chance that a bird will be found to be able to fly" or "if something is a bird it probably can fly". The probabilistic version is also capable of being defeated (it is defeasible), but it includes the idea that the uncertainty might be quantifiable according to axioms of probability. (An exact number need not be attached as in the first example.[12]:?67?)

In some theories, argumentation schemes are mostly schemes for arguments with defeasible inference although there could be schemes for specialized areas of discourse using other forms of inference, such as probability in the sciences.[1]:?1–2? For most or all everyday arguments, the schemes are defeasible.[18]

In other theories, the argumentation schemes are deductive or there is an attempt to interpret the schemes in a probabilistic way.[19]

Examples

[edit]

Argument from expert opinion

[edit]

Argument from expert opinion can be considered a sub-type of the argument from position to know presented at the beginning of the article. In this case, the person who is in a position to know is an expert who knows about some field.[20]

Argument from expert opinion[20]
Major premise: Source E is an expert in subject domain S containing proposition A.
Minor premise: E asserts that proposition A is true (false).
Conclusion: A is true (false).

Critical questions

[edit]

The schemes of Walton (1996) and Walton, Reed & Macagno (2008) come with critical questions. Critical questions are questions that could be asked to throw doubt on the argument's support for its conclusion. They are targeted toward key assumptions that, if true, make the argument acceptable. The reason these assumptions are presented in the form of questions is that these schemes are a part of a dialectical theory of argumentation.[1]:?15? An argument is dialectical when it is a back and forth of argument and rebuttal or questioning. This can be the case even when there is only one reasoner, presenting arguments, then seeking out new information or sources of doubt, or critically probing their own initial assumptions. Since everyday arguments are typically defeasible, this is an approach to strengthening a case over time, testing each element of the case and discarding those parts that do not stand up to scrutiny.[21]:?47,?60? The critical questions for argument from expert opinion, given in Walton, Reed & Macagno (2008), are shown below.

Critical questions for argument from expert opinion[20]
CQ1: Expertise question: How credible is E as an expert source?
CQ2: Field question: Is E an expert in the field that A is in?
CQ3: Opinion question: What did E assert that implies A?
CQ4: Trustworthiness question: Is E personally reliable as a source?
CQ5: Consistency question: Is A consistent with what other experts assert?
CQ6: Backup evidence question: Is E's assertion based on evidence?

Another version of the scheme argument from expert opinion, given in a textbook by Groarke, Tindale & Little (2013), does not include critical questions. Instead more of the key assumptions are included as additional premises of the argument.[22]

Argument from ignorance

[edit]

Argument from ignorance can be stated in a very informal way as, "if it were true, I would know it".[17]:?112? Walton gives the following example of an argument from ignorance: "The posted train schedule says that train 12 to Amsterdam stops at Haarlem and Amsterdam Central Station. We want to determine whether the train stops at Schipol. We can reason as follows: Since the schedule did not indicate that the train stops at Schipol, we can infer that it does not stop at Schipol."[17]:?112? Examples very much like this are well known in computer science discussions about the closed-world assumption for databases.[citation needed] One can assume that the train operating authority has a policy of maintaining a complete database of all of the stops and of publishing accurate schedules. In such cases it is fairly well assured that the information on the published schedule is correct even though it is possible for information to be missing from the database or not included in some particular schedule posting.

The scheme and its accompanying critical questions are shown below.[1]:?327?

Argument from ignorance[20]
Major premise: If A were true, then A would be known to be true.
Minor premise: It is not the case that A is known to be true.
Conclusion: Therefore, A is not true.
Critical questions for argument from ignorance[20]
CQ1: How far along has the search for evidence progressed?
CQ2: Which side has the burden of proof in the dialogue as a whole? In other words, what is the ultimate probandum [claim that is to be proved] and who is supposed to prove it?
CQ3: How strong does the proof need to be in order for this party to be successful in fulfilling the burden?

These critical questions, CQ2 and CQ3 especially, show the dialectical nature of the theory from which this scheme derives (that is, the scheme is based on a back and forth exchange between different parties). Two dialectical concerns are considered. It might be the case, as in some legal systems, that there is a presumption favoring a certain position—e.g., a presumption of innocence favoring the accused.[1]:?98? In that case, the burden of proof is on the accuser, and it would not be proper to argue in the opposite direction: "If the accused were innocent I would have known about it; I don't know about it; therefore, the accused is not innocent." Even if it were a proper argument, the standard of proof in such a case (as asked in CQ3) is very high, beyond a reasonable doubt, but the argument from ignorance alone might be very weak. When challenged, additional arguments would be needed to build a sufficiently strong case.[1]:?35?

Other schemes

[edit]

The following list is a selection of names of argumentation schemes from Walton, Reed & Macagno (2008); other sources may give different names:

  • Argument from witness testimony
  • Argument from popular opinion
  • Argument from popular practice
  • Argument from example
  • Argument from composition
  • Argument from division
  • Argument from oppositions
  • Argument from alternatives
  • Argument from verbal classification
  • Argument from definition to verbal classification
  • Argument from vagueness of a verbal classification
  • Argument from arbitrariness of a verbal classification
  • Argument from interaction of act and person
  • Argument from values
  • Argument from the group and its members
  • Practical reasoning argument
  • Argument from waste
  • Argument from sunk costs
  • Argument from correlation to cause
  • Argument from sign
  • Argument from evidence to a hypothesis
  • Argument from consequences
  • Argument from threat
  • Argument from fear appeal
  • Argument from danger appeal
  • Argument from need for help
  • Argument from distress
  • Argument from commitment
  • Ethotic argument
  • Generic ad hominem argument
  • Pragmatic inconsistency argument
  • Argument from inconsistent commitment
  • Circumstantial ad hominem argument
  • Argument from bias
  • Bias ad hominem argument
  • Argument from gradualism
  • Slippery slope argument

See Practical reason § In argumentation for a description of argumentation schemes for practical reasoning.

Relation to fallacies

[edit]

Many of the names of argumentation schemes may be familiar because of their history as names of fallacies and because of the history of the teaching of fallacies in critical thinking and informal logic courses. In his groundbreaking work, Fallacies, C. L. Hamblin challenged the idea that the traditional fallacies are always fallacious.[23][14]:?25? Subsequently, Walton described the fallacies as kinds of arguments; they can be used properly and provide support for conclusions, support which is, however, provisional and the arguments defeasible. When used improperly they can be fallacious.[24]

Uses

[edit]

Argumentation schemes are used for argument identification, argument analysis, argument evaluation, and argument invention.[25]

Argument identification

[edit]

Argument identification is the identification of arguments in a text or spoken discourse. Many or most of the statements will not be arguments or parts of arguments. But some of those statements might look similar to arguments. Informal logicians have especially noted the similarity between words used to express arguments and those used to express explanations.[26][27] Words like "because" or "since" can be used to introduce reasons that justify argumentative positions, but they can also be used to introduce explanations: e.g., "something is the way it is because of the following explanation". Schemes may aid in argument identification because they describe factors that distinguish the argument type from other text. For example, an argument from expert opinion refers to an expert and a field of expertise, both of which could be identified in a text. Some schemes contain more easily distinguished characteristics than others.

Argument mining

[edit]

Argument mining is the automatic identification of arguments in natural language using computing technology.[28] It also includes some of the tasks of argument analysis.[28]:?57? The same benefits from the use of argumentation schemes as described above for identification and analysis are relevant to argument mining. Linguistic features that distinguish specific schemes can be used by computer algorithms to identify instances of those schemes and therefore automatically identify the arguments that are of those kinds.[28]:?109–113? Without the ability to notice such argumentative patterns, only features common to all arguments would be available. Feng & Hirst (2011) proposed using argumentation schemes to automatically help fill in missing (implicit) premises in arguments, and they experimented with detecting instances of such schemes.[29] Similar work was done by Lawrence and Reed, and reported in 2016.[30]

Argument analysis

[edit]

Argument analysis is distinguishing the premises and conclusion of an argument and determining their relationships (such as whether they are linked or convergent—see Argument map § Key features for diagrams of such relationships), determining the form of inference, and making explicit any implicit premises or conclusions.[12]:?138–171? (These are the tasks of analysis from a logical perspective. When discourse and rhetorical analyses are considered, there would be additional tasks.)

The logical analysis of arguments is especially made difficult by the presence of implicit elements.[13]:?177?[27]:?208–9? Their being implicit means that they are not present in the text (or spoken discourse) as statements; nevertheless, they are understood by the reader or hearer because of nonverbal elements or because of shared background knowledge from the social, cultural, or other shared, context. The implicit elements are also elements that are needed to make the argument cogent. Arguments containing implicit elements are called enthymemes, which is a term that was used by Aristotle in his works about dialectical reasoning and argument.[14]:?18? If an argument appears to match a scheme but is missing some elements, the scheme could be used as a guide to determining what is implicit in the argument.[1]:?189?[29]:?987? An additional challenge with regard to this task could be that some schemes are easy to confuse. In Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca's concept of argumentative scheme, different schemes could apply to the same argument depending on the interpretation of the argument or the argument could be described by multiple schemes.[13]:?187–88? Hansen and Walton also write that arguments may fit multiple schemes.[31]

Argument evaluation

[edit]

Argument evaluation is the determination of the goodness of the argument: determining how good the argument is and whether, or with what reservations, it ought to be accepted. As mentioned above, in schemes accompanied by critical questions, a measure of the goodness of the argument is whether the critical questions can be appropriately answered. In other schemes, as in the example of the versions of argument from expert opinion in Groarke, Tindale & Little (2013), only good arguments fit the scheme because the criteria for goodness are included as premises,[32] so if any one of the premises is false, the conclusion should not be accepted.

Argument invention

[edit]

Argument invention is making new arguments to suit the occasion. As mentioned above, Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca attribute that use to the loci and topoi of the classical argumentation theorists.[13][14]:?20? They form a catalog of argument types from which arguers may draw in constructing their arguments. With argumentation schemes described by their structure with single letter variables as placeholders, constructing such arguments is just a matter of filling in the placeholders. The arguer could use other words that convey the same meaning and embellish the argument in other ways.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i Walton, Douglas N.; Reed, Chris; Macagno, Fabrizio (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511802034. ISBN 9780521897907. OCLC 181424052.
  2. ^ Eemeren, Frans H. van, ed. (2001). Crucial concepts in argumentation theory. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. ISBN 905356523X. OCLC 49333598.
  3. ^ Braet, Antoine C. (March 2005). "The common topic in Aristotle's Rhetoric: precursor of the argumentation scheme". Argumentation. 19 (1): 65–83. doi:10.1007/s10503-005-2313-x. S2CID 145642868. See also: Aristotle (1991) [4th century BCE]. On rhetoric: a theory of civic discourse. Translated by Kennedy, George A. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195064865. OCLC 22629945.
  4. ^ van Eemeren, Frans H.; Grootendorst, Rob (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: a pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 9780805810691. OCLC 24792772.
  5. ^ Toulmin, Stephen; Rieke, Richard D.; Janik, Allan (1984) [1979]. An introduction to reasoning. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company. ISBN 9780024211606. OCLC 9783951.
  6. ^ Kienpointner, Manfred (1992). Alltagslogik: Struktur und Funktion von Argumentationsmustern. Problemata (in German). Vol. 126. Stuttgart: Fromman-Holzboog. ISBN 9783772814624. OCLC 28724121.
  7. ^ Aristotle (1997) [4th century BCE]. Topics. Clarendon Aristotle series. Translated by Smith, Robin. Oxford; New York: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198239420. OCLC 34411586.
  8. ^ Boethius (1978) [522–23 BCE]. Boethius's De topicis differentiis. Translated by Stump, Eleonore. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ISBN 9780801410673. OCLC 3414358.
  9. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius (2003) [44 BCE]. Topica. Oxford classical monographs. Translated by Reinhardt, Tobias. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199263462. OCLC 54071435.
  10. ^ Eemeren, Frans H. van; Grootendorst, Rob; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; et al. (1996). Fundamentals of argumentation theory: a handbook of historical backgrounds and contemporary developments. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 9780805818611. OCLC 33970847. It draws its data, assumptions, and methods from disciplines as disparate as formal logic and discourse analysis, linguistics and forensic science, philosophy and psychology, political science and education, sociology and law, and rhetoric and artificial intelligence.
  11. ^ Rigotti, Eddo; Greco Morasso, Sara (2019). Inference in argumentation: a topics-based approach to argument schemes. Argumentation library. Vol. 34. Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-04568-5. ISBN 9783030045661. OCLC 1096259194. S2CID 125412473.
  12. ^ a b c d e f Walton, Douglas N. (2006). Fundamentals of critical argumentation. Critical reasoning and argumentation. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511807039. ISBN 0521823196. OCLC 57434163.
  13. ^ a b c d e f g h i Perelman, Cha?m; Olbrechts-Tyteca, Lucie (1969) [1958]. The new rhetoric: a treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. OCLC 21425.
  14. ^ a b c d e Eemeren, Frans H. van; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2014). Handbook of argumentation theory (Revised ed.). New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5. ISBN 9789048194728. OCLC 871004444.
  15. ^ Walton, Reed & Macagno 2008, p. 3; Hastings, Arthur Claude (August 1962). A reformulation of the modes of reasoning in argumentation (Ph.D. thesis). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University. OCLC 18518112. ProQuest 288066554. For extensive review of the history, see also Walton, Reed & Macagno 2008, chapter 8 and section 7.3 for information about Hastings' treatment of argumentation schemes.
  16. ^ Toulmin, Stephen (2003) [1958]. The uses of argument (Updated ed.). Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511840005. ISBN 0521827485. OCLC 51607421.
  17. ^ a b c Walton, Douglas N. (1996). Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 9780805820713. OCLC 32704843.
  18. ^ Walton, Douglas N. (2004). "Defeasible modus ponens arguments". Abductive reasoning. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press. p. 122. ISBN 0817314415. OCLC 55044871.
  19. ^ For deductive and probabilistic, see sections 2.1 and 5 in: Lumer, Christoph (May 2011). "Argument schemes—an epistemological approach". In Zenker, Frank (ed.). Argumentation: cognition & community: 9th biennial conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation, May 18–21, 2011, University of Windsor. OSSA 9. Windsor: Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation. pp. 1–32. ISBN 9780920233665. OCLC 843227451. For another probabilistic approach, see section 6 in: Hahn, Ulrike; Oaksford, Mike; Harris, Adam J. L. (2013). "Testimony and argument: a Bayesian perspective". In Zenker, Frank (ed.). Bayesian argumentation: the practical side of probability. Synthese library. Vol. 362. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 15–38. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-5357-0_2. ISBN 9789400753563. OCLC 826657415. And: Hahn, Ulrike; Hornikx, Jos (June 2016). "A normative framework for argument quality: argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation". Synthese. 193 (6): 1833–1873. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0815-0. hdl:2066/160400. S2CID 255062152.
  20. ^ a b c d e Tables from Walton, Reed & Macagno 2008, p. 310.
  21. ^ Rescher, Nicholas (1977). Dialectics: a controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press. ISBN 087395372X. OCLC 3034395.
  22. ^ Groarke, Leo; Tindale, Christopher W.; Little, J. Frederick (2013) [1997]. Good reasoning matters!: a constructive approach to critical thinking (5th ed.). Don Mills, Ont.; Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195445756. OCLC 799130281.
  23. ^ See chapter 1 in: Hamblin, Charles Leonard (1993) [1970]. Fallacies. Studies in critical thinking and informal logic. Vol. 1. Newport News, VA: Vale Press. ISBN 9780916475246. OCLC 29690976.
  24. ^ Bench-Capon, Trevor; Atkinson, Katie (2010). "Argumentation schemes: from informal logic to computational models" (PDF). In Reed, Chris; Tindale, Christopher W. (eds.). Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation: an examination of Douglas Walton's theories of reasoning and argument. Tributes. Vol. 12. London: College Publications. pp. 103–114. ISBN 9781848900059. OCLC 648095461.
  25. ^ Janjua, Naeem Khalid (2014). "Argumentation life cycle". A defeasible logic programming-based framework to support argumentation in semantic web applications. Springer theses. Cham; New York: Springer. p. 33. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-03949-7. hdl:20.500.11937/2073. ISBN 9783319039480. OCLC 895194510.
  26. ^ Hansen, Hans V.; Walton, Douglas N. (January 2013). "Argument kinds and argument roles in the Ontario provincial election, 2011". Journal of Argumentation in Context. 2 (2): 226–258. doi:10.1075/jaic.2.2.03han. SSRN 2334864. Section 6.5.
  27. ^ a b Walton, Douglas N. (March 2019). "Argumentation schemes & their application in argument mining". In Blair, J. Anthony (ed.). Studies in critical thinking. Windsor Studies in Argumentation. Vol. 8. Windsor: Centre for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric, University of Windsor. pp. 177–211. doi:10.22329/wsia.08.2019. ISBN 9780920233863. OCLC 1125160111.
  28. ^ a b c Stede, Manfred; Schneider, Jodi (2018). Argumentation mining. Synthesis lectures on human language technologies. Vol. 40. San Rafael, CA: Morgan & Claypool. pp. 1–191. doi:10.2200/S00883ED1V01Y201811HLT040. ISBN 9781681734590. OCLC 1083530996.
  29. ^ a b Feng, Vanessa Wei; Hirst, Graeme (June 2011). "Classifying arguments by scheme" (PDF). Proceedings of the 49th annual meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics: human language technologies, 19 June 2011, Portland, Oregon, USA. ACL HLT. Stroudsburg, PA: Association for Computational Linguistics. pp. 987–996. ISBN 9781932432879. OCLC 1150262180.
  30. ^ Lawrence, John; Reed, Chris (September 2016). "Argument mining using argumentation scheme structures" (PDF). In Baroni, Pietro; Gordon, Thomas F.; Scheffler, Tatjana; Stede, Manfred (eds.). Computational models of argument: proceedings of COMMA 2016. Frontiers in artificial intelligence and applications. Vol. 287. Amsterdam: IOS Press. pp. 379–390. doi:10.3233/978-1-61499-686-6-379. ISBN 9781614996859. OCLC 957551747. S2CID 29571966.
  31. ^ Hansen & Walton 2013, section 7.3.
  32. ^ Hansen, Hans V. (2019). Argument scheme theory. Third European conference on argumentation (ECA), June 24–June 27, 2019, Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands: proceedings.

Further reading

[edit]
IOM是什么意思 usp是什么意思 右手心痒是什么预兆 眼睛疼用什么药 软下疳是什么症状
省亲是什么意思 舌头挂什么科 精子是什么颜色的 为什么大便拉不出来 脐疝是什么
9月1号什么星座 两肺纹理增粗是什么意思 龟头有点痒擦什么药 阴囊长白毛是什么原因 夜盲症吃什么
白居易有什么之称 长期喝奶粉有什么好处 壁虎长什么样 四什么八什么的成语 什么是呼吸性碱中毒
色相是什么意思hcv9jop6ns9r.cn 内痔用什么药hcv8jop6ns6r.cn 耳石症挂什么科hcv9jop6ns0r.cn yl是什么牌子hcv9jop7ns2r.cn 料酒是什么酒hcv9jop6ns7r.cn
打耳洞不能吃什么hcv8jop2ns0r.cn 肠炎吃什么hcv9jop5ns4r.cn jojo什么意思hcv7jop6ns7r.cn 数字3五行属什么hcv8jop0ns4r.cn 阴虚火旺吃什么水果hcv9jop7ns2r.cn
什么茶不能喝脑筋急转弯hcv9jop5ns4r.cn 维字五行属什么hcv7jop5ns3r.cn 什么是阳光抑郁症hcv7jop5ns2r.cn 空调送风模式有什么用hcv8jop0ns4r.cn cn是什么意思啊hcv9jop6ns0r.cn
为什么不hcv8jop3ns9r.cn 过生日送什么礼物好hcv9jop4ns2r.cn sakura是什么牌子hcv8jop9ns0r.cn 吃鱼对身体有什么好处imcecn.com 幽门阳性是什么意思hcv7jop6ns9r.cn
百度